Making and managing medical anomalies: Exploring the classification of ‘medically unexplained symptoms’, 2020, Rasmussen

Andy

Senior Member (Voting rights)
Yeah, I'm not going to worry about the profession getting justice..
This article explores the making and management of anomaly in scientific work, taking ‘medically unexplained symptoms’ (MUS) as its case. MUS is a category used to characterize health conditions that are widely held to be ambiguous, in terms of their nature, causes and treatment. It has been suggested that MUS is a ‘wastebasket diagnosis’. However, although a powerful metaphor, it does neither the category nor the profession justice: Unlike waste in a wastebasket, unexplained symptoms are not discarded but contained, not ejected but managed. Rather than a ‘wastebasket’, I propose that we instead think about it as a ‘junk drawer’. A junk drawer is an ordering device whose function is the containment of things we want to keep but have nowhere else to put. Based on a critical document analysis of the research literature on MUS (107 research articles from 10 medical journals, published 2001–2016), the article explores how the MUS category is constituted and managed as a junk drawer in medical science.
Paywall, https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/0306312720940405
Sci hub, https://sci-hub.tw/10.1177/0306312720940405
 
rs=w:1240,h:620,cg:true


https://cfsgraphics.com/
 
I've drifted at high speed through this rather dense article that seems to use a lot of words to say that MUS is a problem, that it's an anomaly in biomedicine because it's symptoms without signs, that this is solved by passing it over to psychiatry who can't explain it either, but that's OK so long as they can help the patients.

Is this another version of the Sharpe/Grecko 'illness without disease' paper? I'm confused. Here's my attempt at picking out some relevant bits. I might have completely missed the point.

Here's my version with some quotes.

Start by assuming MUS is a real category worth researching and claim there's lots of research happening:
Yet medically unexplained symptoms are continually and increasingly the object of clinical research. Paradoxically, then, despite being first partially then completely excluded from the formalized medical classification systems, the MUS category is increasingly enlisted in medical research and is thus steadily becoming a central medical category; it is pushed to the fringe yet drawn towards the centre of medical science.
Then waffle a lot about classification and anomalies to confuse your reader and sound erudite, then do a limited literature search and discover most of is it in psychosomatic journals:
Judging by the publication rates in the journals sampled, the MUS category is used mostly in the context of psychiatric and primary care research (most frequently in the former) (177/60), though MUS is invoked in psychosomatic contexts more often than in psychiatry in general
Draw some conclusions from the research you've sampled:
Various definitions of MUS listed, all summed up as
...premised on the co-occurrence of present symptoms and absent signs. ...
MUS may thus be characterized as anomalies constituted by their lack of fit with scientific biomedicine, by their violation of expectations induced by the biomedical paradigm. ...
...discordance’ between what the patient says and what the doctor can find must thus be accounted for.
Waffle some more about categories and paradigms:
The analysis has demonstrated how MUS is constituted as a ‘junk drawer category’, and how this category is managed in medical research. First, I have shown that the core criterion of MUS as a category is the co-occurrence of present somatic symptoms and absent somatic signs of disease, and that, fundamentally, this criterion is an expression that MUS violate expectations induced by the biomedical paradigm. Biomedicine as epistemic convention is therefore causally implicated in making symptoms anomalous and this ‘paradigm-induced’ anomalous character is what constitutes MUS as a category. In other words, the junk drawer is constituted as a contravention of the existing order. The majority of articles, however, hide the constitutive role of biomedicine, making the core criterion an ontological fact about the symptoms, rather than an epistemic fact about the beliefs and practices of the profession. Thus, the nature of the MUS category as a junk drawer is concealed.
And conclude that MUS is only anomalous if we try to explain it with biomedicine.

The implication being that biomedicine may be the wrong model, so bring in psychiatry instead and talk about the problem that patients don't like this?
Regarding puzzle solving, historians of science and others suggest that when anomalous phenomena are not simply ignored or discarded, scientists will typically try somehow to make them fit in by making slight adjustments or creating new categories to the established order, or by proposing rule-exceptions that dampen or remove the anomalous character. These strategies are called ‘monster-adjustment’ (Bloor, 1978). There are strong indications of a move towards such strategies in the sample, in the form of assumptions that unexplained physical symptoms are really symptoms of mental distress (e.g. Jutel, 2010). Such assumptions are criticized in the sample (e.g. 5-3) but not nearly as often as they are taken for granted. They come to the fore, for instance, in the conviction that psychiatric therapy is appropriate for but hampered by uncooperative patients (e.g. 6-5; 11-7) or in the fact that only two articles in the sample actually investigate new hypotheses that MUS have somatic causes (7-9; 8-5). As indicated in the analysis, the connection with somatization is one way this assumption seeps through. Other ways are through concepts that carry similar psychogenic assumptions – such as ‘alexithymia’ (2-3), ‘illness perceptions’ (9-10), and ‘somatovisceral illusions’ (1-16), each indicating that the patients have misunderstood the nature of their symptoms. As such, psychogenic assumptions are part of the biomedical doxa and the commitment to make MUS ‘fit in’. They may be interpreted as a form of monster-adjustment, pushing for the resolution of the anomalous character of present symptoms without signs. This interpretation of MUS as caused by a misunderstanding on the patient’s part has been criticized by some social scientists as a form of blame-shifting (e.g. Horton-Salway, 2002; Jutel, 2010). Others have been more cautious.

And trick patients into accepting psych treatment in order to show them it works?
Greco (2012: 2365) warns against any knee-jerk criticism of psychogenic assumptions by social scientists. She argues that the medical profession might be right to treat MUS as psychogenic and that the question must be settled empirically. Inasmuch as ‘right’ indicates that it could work, I agree. However, from what evidence there is, it does not seem to do the trick: An important context where psychogenic assumptions are expressed is when researchers complain that Rasmussen 19 patients reject psychiatric treatment (e.g. 6-5; 11-7). Undeterred, researchers have experimented with the reframing of psychiatric treatment as somatic treatment, trying to get patients into disguised psychiatric treatment (e.g. 8-8, 2013: 300). In one study, this strategy is unashamedly presented as ‘a Trojan horse’ (6-6, 2011: 3) – without considering the risk that patients will learn to fear the GPs when they come bearing ‘therapeutic gifts’.
And if that doesn't work, keep experimenting?
Somatization in its varieties has yet to succeed as a monster-adjusting strategy. Moreover, due to recent changes whereby all SD diagnoses have been ejected from formal classifications (American Psychiatric Association, 2013), the strategy might have to change. But that is the beauty of a ‘junk drawer category’: They can try again later.

And perhaps try harder to refine the definition of MUS to make a more homogeneous research cohort?
Formalizing a set of criteria, for instance relating to symptom count, impact and persistence, or the frequency of attendance, would probably enable researchers to study a more homogenous patient group than current practices allow for. However, standardized criteria do not necessarily make classification homogenous, as they must nevertheless be interpreted and applied in the course of situated practice

But what if you disagree about what is explained and what is unexplained?
Moreover, there are reasons to believe that what I call the core criterion is itself a major source of variation: studies indicate that even when criteria are formalized and shared, doctors disagree about where to draw the line between the explained and unexplained (e.g. Creed and Barsky, 2004: 404) – not least because they also disagree about the distinction between diseases and non-diseases (Smith, 2002; Tikkinen et al., 2012). This indicates a less than clear-cut line between the explained and the unexplained.

So maybe this whole field is a mess and you need to throw out all that psychosomatic stuff and think again?
Standardizing the classification of MUS would therefore require a more thorough reflection over basic concepts such as disease, objective evidence and medical explanation. The potential advantage of doing so would be the ability to determine the value of MUS as a medical category – to test whether it is sensible and helpful to group patients based primarily on their lack of fit with the biomedical paradigm.
 
Patients with MUS are highly unpopular, as indicated by medicine’s use of unflattering monikers such as ‘frequent flyers’, ‘thick folder patients’ (Greco, 2012) and ‘heart-sink patients’
I am not even shocked anymore but still, the reality of this is so grotesque as to be unbelievable. Because this is exactly the reason why no progress can be made on those issues. It's a circular problem, where the problem cannot be solved because it fixes itself into the same position and refuses to budge, like two interlocked gears.

The only professional comparison that can be made is the similarly grotesque display of police violence on US streets, where police beat up and murder innocent people in cold blood with no accountability, even when it's captured on camera. There is no other comparable display of base unprofessionalism in any other profession, especially one leading to mass suffering and death.

But I think a prison camp would be a more apt metaphor. The diagnoses may be junked in a drawer but behind those diagnoses are tens of millions real people whose lives are effectively bound, tortured and killed. Legally. By medical professionals. This can't happen without full dehumanization, which is incompatible with the practice of medicine, or just basic morality.

Because worse of all is the rejection of consent, the trampling over not only informed consent but actual firm and rational dissent. Any government behaving this way would be labeled as ruthless and tyrannical, probably on the receiving end of massive international sanctions. But complaining only brings more binding and more torture and more death. The beatings will continue until morale is shown to have statistically improved on an arbitrary questionnaire.
 
"MUS is only anomalous if we try to explain it with biomedicine."

If you asked a homeopath, naturopath, traditional chinese medicine practitioner, faith healer, and similar alternative medicine practitioners to explain why a patient has MUS, I'm sure they would often be able to come up with an explanation that makes perfect sense in the theoretical framework of their discipline.

Coming up with some sort of theoretical explanation is easy and people do it all the time. Finding the correct explanation is hard.

PS: like that psychoanalyst who explained CFS in a psychoanalystical framework as one's sexual energy not being expressed or something to that extent, I don't recall the exact details.
 
Last edited:
I have just been thinking a bit more about this bit:
Formalizing a set of criteria, for instance relating to symptom count, impact and persistence, or the frequency of attendance, would probably enable researchers to study a more homogenous patient group than current practices allow for.

This method of categorisation seems to me at about the same scientific level as this:
f49b41c7aa7f702bfba8126a43a47dcc.jpg


Edit: Crossposted with Strategist. Looks like we agree.
 
It seems that Erik Rasmussen is a young social worker with a pony tail and shaggy beard who has perhaps realised that he has wandered into the doo-doo of liaison psychiatry and pass-the-buckology.

Maybe this is his attempt at saying as politely as he can, i.e. not to get himself sacked next week, that MUS is drivel.
Maybe not.
 
I used to have the diagnosis of fibromyalgia for which the rheum at the time (1996) said merely: use heat, heat, heat. Still good advice.

But now the ICD-10 code for fibromyalgia is termed Widespread Chronic Pain, which tells you less, much less. Another tiny compartment of the junk drawer.

At least with fibromyalga (for which I discerned I was going to have to come up with every suggestion of med or treatment, which I succesfully did, as the rebellious disabled nurse that I was and am) you have a category that contains all sorts of associated symptoms, which is useful. Is 'widespread chronic pain' somehow more accurate, or finely delineating a wide-assortment of symptoms seen in fibro? No, it isn't and doesn't.

MUS basket is a nightmare for the patient, a joke for the so-called 'professionals.' Only when the doctor's wife or daughter or son or nephew comes down with a disease hidden in the MUS junk drawer (if they can find it in there with all the muck), will that sole clinician change his mind about this nonsense nomenclature.
 
There was an article about Rasmussen last year on a news site about research, where he says chronic fatigue syndrome is included in his drawer. Don't know if that's stated also in the now published paper. We discussed it a bit in the Scandinavia thread here

I'll insert the first post about that news article in this thread, so people don't have to click to read it.
I translated the word he uses in Norwegian (roteskuff) as "clutter drawer", I can't believe he went for "junk drawer". Well, it's bad either way..

Forskning.no a Norwegian news site about research had an article the other day about the HRA report supposedly clearing the PACE trial from all criticism (discussed in the general PACE thread here) . Today the university OsloMet has an article about MUS (medically unexplained symptoms) turning into Bodily Distress Syndrome, and that Chronic Fatigue Syndrome belongs under this umbrella term.

At least they're honest about what they think when they say the main criteria for Bodily Distress Disorder is that the doctor think the patient is too focused on their symptoms.

The google translation is as usual not very good, but feel free to ask if you want a translation done by a human of some words/sections. "Root box" for instance is "roteskuff" - a drawer for bits and pieces you don't know where else to put. I've translated it as a "clutter drawer". The scientist seems to think putting patients in such a drawer is a huge improvement from putting them in a garbage bin...

MUPS is not in itself a diagnosis, but a collective term. In the literature, MUPS has been referred to as a garbage bin in the diagnostic system. Rasmussen also suggests that this category can be understood as a clutter drawer.

- In the garbage bin you put something you want to get rid of. Though too many patients unfortunately often feel treated as garbage, I mean the clutter drawer is more precise. In a clutter drawer you put something you do not want to throw, at least not at first, but which you have no other places to put.

The medical researchers are working actively to get order in the clutter drawer, but so far have not succeeded, says Rasmussen.

...
The new version of the hospital's diagnostic manual contains a new diagnosis that is intended to embrace several of the patients in the drawer. The diagnosis bears the name Bodily Distress Disorder. It is intended to replace a number of diagnoses for disorders that cause bodily symptoms that can vary from mild to significant, without the presence of a bodily disease, so-called somatoform disorders.

- It is too early to say anything about how the new diagnosis will work. One of the main criteria is that the doctor thinks the patient is too concerned about their symptoms. It is possible to envision that such a diagnosis will not be particularly popular among patients, Erik Børve Rasmussen concludes.


Forskning.no: Lider du av MUPS?
google translation: Do you suffer from MUS?
 
If you asked a homeopath, naturopath, traditional chinese medicine practitioner, faith healer, and similar alternative medicine practitioners to explain why a patient has MUS
I've always thought that psych explanations of my illness make about as much sense as misaligned chakras or negative chi energy. Only difference is that doctors and psychs get to parade their ideas around as "Evidence based medicine".
 
Maybe this is his attempt at saying as politely as he can, i.e. not to get himself sacked next week, that MUS is drivel.
I'm inclined to agree with @Jonathan Edwards on this (though the language is so dense I couldn't be sure).

The article looks at how the terms MUS, Somatisation, FSS, etc are used in the literature and operationalised in research.
Conclusion: very inconsistently, basically everybody makes up their own definition.
Worse, few researchers even realise this and merrily go on to compare apples with oranges.
medical scientists seem unaware of the tremendous variations in their management of the MUS category
So this paper is actually quite important in pointing out the mess. Pity it's written in such dense language few will bother to plough through it (it always seems ironic to me that the social sciences, of all disciplines, should favour such impenetrable expression - not very socially minded).

The author surveys what's out there; the fact that much of it is horrifying is not his fault. He gives little indication of what he thinks of it himself, apart from his main point that the whole MUS construct is highly inconsistent. There's a hint here though:
This interpretation of MUS as caused by a misunderstanding on the patient’s part has been criticized by some social scientists as a form of blame-shifting (e.g. Horton-Salway, 2002; Jutel, 2010). Others have been more cautious. Greco (2012: 2365) warns against any knee-jerk criticism of psychogenic assumptions by social scientists. She argues that the medical profession might be right to treat MUS as psychogenic and that the question must be settled empirically.

Inasmuch as ‘right’ indicates that it could work, I agree. However, from what evidence there is, it does not seem to do the trick: An important con-text where psychogenic assumptions are expressed is when researchers complain that patients reject psychiatric treatment (e.g. 6-5; 11-7). Undeterred, researchers have experi-mented with the reframing of psychiatric treatment as somatic treatment, trying to get patients into disguised psychiatric treatment (e.g. 8-8, 2013: 300). In one study, this strat-egy is unashamedly presented as ‘a Trojan horse’ (6-6, 2011: 3) – without considering the risk that patients will learn to fear the GPs when they come bearing ‘therapeutic gifts’
 
From the same author:

Rasmussen, Erik & Ro, Karin. (2018). How general practitioners understand and handle medically unexplained symptoms: A focus group study. BMC Family Practice. 19. 10.1186/s12875-018-0745-2.

"The biomedical frame emphasised the lack of objective evidence, problematized subjective patient testimony, and manifested [general practitioners'] feelings of uncertainty, doubt and powerlessness. This in turn complicated [general practitioners'] patient handling.


"In contrast, the biopsychosocial frame emphasised clinical experience, turned patient testimony into a valuable source of information, and manifested [general practitioners'] feelings of confidence and competence. This in turn made them [= general practitioners] feel empowered. [...]

"The biopsychosocial frame helps GPs to understand and handle MUS better than the biomedical frame does. Medical students should spend more time learning biopsychosocial medicine, and to integrate the clinical knowledge of their peers with their own."


Reserach Gate link here.
Link to BMC paper here .

(Edited to fix links.)
 
Last edited:
"In contrast, the biopsychosocial frame emphasised clinical experience, turned patient testimony into a valuable source of information, and manifested feelings of confidence and competence. This in turn made them [= general practitioners] feel empowered. [...]

Are they having a laugh? BPS turned patient testimony into a valuable source of information?

I don't give a rat's a$$ if my GP feels empowered. My appointment is about me not him. If he wants it to be about him he shoukd go make his own appointment with someone else!

FFS!
 
"In contrast, the biopsychosocial frame emphasised clinical experience, turned patient testimony into a valuable source of information, and manifested [general practitioners'] feelings of confidence and competence. This in turn made them [= general practitioners] feel empowered. [...]
Literally the exact opposite. Fascinating. Down is up. Success is failure. Death is life. Pain is too much joy trying to burst out all at once.

BPS is basically a hagiographic story physicians tell themselves, a narrative where they are the hero and nothing else matters. The patients certainly don't matter, we could be replaced with blocks of wood for all that it matters.

Then they are in turn frustrated because it's all a delusion and it doesn't work at all, but the frustration is further taken on the patients. Which, somehow, usually ends up concluding that it further validates the BPS model, because it needs constant affirmation of its glory.

I'm very interested in politics and how weird it can get, especially in authoritarianism, and frankly this is right up there with the weirdest stuff of all, real Death of Stalin stuff, except not actual satire but actual death and suffering.
 
Back
Top